Susan Stebbing and the language of common sense – CHAPMAN (Ph)

CHAPMAN, S. Susan Stebbing and the language of common sense. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013. Resenha de: GIAROLO, Kariel Antonio. Philósophos, Goiânia, v. 23, n. 1, p.161-169, jan./jun, 2018.

Lizzie Susan Stebbing (1885-1943) was an important figure in the beginning of the twentieth century, specially in view of her role in the development of analytic philosophy and particularly because she was the first woman Professor of Philosophy in a British university. In Susan Stebbing and the Language of Common Sense, Siobhan Chapman, Professor of English at the University of Liverpool (UK), brings us a de-tailed historical analysis of Stebbing’s life and of her philo-sophical developments. The book, divided into nine chapters, provides a lot of information on Stebbing’s per-sonal, academic and political life as well as on her philo-sophical ideas and commitments. Given that, for a better analysis of the book it is possible to divide it into three main parts: (i) historical importance of Stebbing; (ii) philo-sophical context of her academic life; and (iii) importance of her philosophical conceptions, mainly, the logical-linguistic.

Stebbing was born in 1885 and she was registered in Barnet, in London. About her young life, Chapman (2013, p.10) says that she was a delicate child, suffering from an illness called Menière’s Disease. Her ill health and periods of enforced inactivity continued into her adult life and many times she was unable to work because of this unstable health. In the first years, because she wasn’t strong enough for full-time schooling, she was educated privately at home and afterwards she went to James Allen’s Girl’s School, in London. After finishing high school, she was admitted at Girton College in Cambridge, and she graduated in 1908. Finishing College in Cambridge, she went to King’s Col-lege, London, to take her MA in Moral Science, until 1912.

As a student, Stebbing was influenced by the works of F. H. Bradley, B. Russell, A. F. Whitehead and, mainly, G. E. Moore. In her first philosophical works she shows a great interest in analytical philosophy, specially the relations be-tween natural language and formal logic. Furthermore, at that time she demonstrated a great interest in debates be-tween idealists and realists, and even in her young life she showed an ambitious personality, trying to identify the mis-takes in the two approaches. Her MA’s thesis was entitled Pragmatism and French Voluntarism and already in this initial work she indicates her commitments with the relations be-tween the notions of action, language and the theory of knowledge. Stebbing argued, as explained by Chapman (p. 28), that action and thought, intellect and will cannot be opposed. This is significant because in her mature books, the relations between natural language, formal logic and the purposes of speech are recurrent and a guide to understand her main philosophical conceptions.

According to Chapman (p. 37) during the decade or so following her MA graduation, Stebbing established herself as an important voice in the philosophical discussions in Cambridge and London. She was engaged in debates with the leading philosophic figures in Britain at that time and her work was read and discussed frequently by them. In 1931 she became president of the Mind Association and a few years later of the Aristotelian Society. Due to the in-crease of her reputation and the quality of her work, in the summer of 1933, Susan Stebbing was honoured with a place at the University of London as Professor of Philoso-phy. However, if today a woman being a Professor in a University stands as a normal fact, at that time it was not trivial: Stebbing was the first woman Professor of Philosophy in a University in Great Britain. Women’s rights in the ninetieth and twenti-eth centuries were limited, including the positions in uni-versities. For this reason, Stebbing can be considered as a milestone in the fight for equal rights between men and women. Chapman, in several instances, particularly in the first chapters, calls attention to this event. In Chapter Four (p. 79) she says: “In its historical and cultural context, Stebbing’s appointment as full Professor of Philosophy real-ly was headline news. Women were by now an established presence, although certainly a minority one, in academia, but their place there was hard-won and still controversial”. Unfortunately, as expect, her appointment did not please everyone.

Anyway, Stebbing remained Professor in London until 1938. During this period, she published several books on logic and language. The most important books are A Mod-ern Introduction to Logic (1930, 1933, the first edition was published before the appointment), Philosophy and The Phys-icists (1937), Thinking to some purpose (1939, the most popu-lar of her books), Ideals and Illusions (1941) and A Modern Elementary Logic (1943). In all these, Stebbing focuses on a logical analysis of the natural language and related issues.

The philosophical context of the beginning of twenti-eth century in Britain was predominantly influenced by an-alytical philosophy. The new developments in logic and language arrived in philosophical discussions and the ana-lytic methodology became the common ground for solving classical problems. Frege, Russell, Moore, Carnap, Wittgen-stein and others were the central figures in that time (in logical and analytical context, of course) and their works changed the way in which philosophical questions were considered. The mathematical logic was a development of traditional Aristotelian syllogistic and one of its main goals was to construct a formal language for science that would be able to avoid the errors and imperfections of natural language. The basic idea was that with a perfect formal lan-guage to express thought it would be possible to solve phil-osophical problems, because many of these problems actually originated in our imperfect ordinary language use.

Susan Stebbing’s academic formation was basically ana-lytical and she read and kept direct contact with some of these figures, in particular, Moore and Russell. In A Modern Introduction to Logic, for instance, Stebbing introduces the recent developments in mathematical logic. According to Chapman (p. 50), “Stebbing proceeds to offer her readers an overview both of traditional Aristotelian logic and of re-cent developments, and also to introduce them to some of the current issues in scientific method, including the prob-lems surrounding deduction and induction”. In this sense, Stebbing is located in a transitional moment in the history of logic: before Frege and Russell, logic was equated with the Aristotelian syllogistic; after them mathematical logic became central. Stebbing, despite her acceptance of math-ematical logic, affords space in her books to the traditional logical analysis as well.

Chapman’s Chapter 4 and, mainly, Chapter 5 present a detailed reconstruction of the philosophical context in which Stebbing worked. Chapter 5, Logical Positivism and Philosophy of Language, is an excellent read for everyone who wants to know more about logical positivism, particularly because Wittgenstein (an “associate” of the Vienna Circle) was of great influence in Stebbing’s conceptions and also because the first time that Carnap went to UK was by invi-tation of Stebbing. The relations between Stebbing and the positivists was closer, but also have several philosophical disagreements. According to Chapman (p. 84) in Logical Positivism and Analysis (1933), she sets out what she sees as the main claims of the logical positivism. For her the most attractive characteristic in Wittgenstein and in the logical positivists was “the insistence on analysis as the philoso-pher’s main tool in searching for clarity and unmasking as simply nonsensical some of the questions that philosophers had traditionally posed themselves”. To the Vienna Circle, the analysis of the sentences can show what sentences have meaning and what sentences haven’t. A sentence is mean-ingful only in one of the three following cases: (i) if it is an-alytic, i.e., if this meaning is determined by the language; (ii) if it is a logical or mathematics sentence; or (iii) if it can be, in principle, verified by observation.

Although Stebbing agreed with some of the positivists ideas, she was a critic of other aspects of their philosophical conceptions, in special the conception of analysis. Accord-ing to her, the way in which the positivists perform analysis is problematic. Positivist approaches fail to observe differ-ent kinds of analysis. They consider that all analysis is nec-essarily linguistic analysis. As Chapman explains (p. 85), “for Stebbing, using language to analyse language involves philosophers in an unproductive and circular activity”. Fur-thermore, the purpose of analysis is to clarify existing be-liefs, not justify them. Another point of disagreement with the members of the Vienna Circle was about metaphysics. For them, all metaphysical sentences haven’t cognitive con-tent: metaphysical sentences are unable to fall in any of the three kinds listed before. They are not analytical, not logical and not observable, in principle, by experience. On the other hand, due the influence of Wittgenstein and Ber-trand Russell, Stebbing sustains an atomistic conception of propositions, namely, that there are basic atomic sentences that constitute the world.

The popularity of Stebbing grew in the 1940’s especially because of Thinking to Some Purpose (1939). In this book, she presents a rich analysis of the way that we think and how we can avoid the illogicalities in the speech of other people and in our own. Written at the beginning of the World War II, the book affords space to discuss some “examples taken from the speeches of politicians and from politically loaded newspaper reports and is explicitly aimed at promot-ing a discerning and critical attitude in the electorate” (p. 120). So, the book, focuses, among other things, also in the political context of England when WWII started.

However, the central idea is that we need to make clear our reasoning and a logical analysis of the ordinary speech could show where the mistakes are. The point is very sim-ple: we talk unclearly, because we think unclearly. Then, to talk in a clear way, we need to consider the way that we think. According to Stebbing (1939, p.22), thinking logical-ly (reflexively) is thinking to some purpose. In her own words, “to pursue an aim without considering what its real-izations would involves is stupid”. In this sense, thinking involves asking questions and trying to find answers to these questions. When we think logically, we think rele-vantly to the purpose that initiated the thinking. The pro-cess of reflective thinking consists in pondering upon a set of facts so as to elicit their connections. This process is known as inferring. The various stages in the process are re-lated to the conclusion as the grounds upon which it is based. Stebbing calls these grounds “premises”. In short, ef-fective thinking is directed to an end. Consequently, there is a teleological commitment in all properly reflexive think-ing.

According to Chapman (p. 183), Stebbing was con-cerned in special with the analysis of language primarily as a window to the process of thinking that it expressed. By the language we can determine if this process is logical or oth-erwise. Books like A Modern Introduction to Logic (1930), Thinking to Some Purpose (1939), Ideals and Illusions (1941) and A Modern Elementary Logic (1943) contains some im-portant ideas which became central in subsequent discus-sions in Ordinary Language Philosophy and in Pragmatics. Stebbing’s philosophical motivations were very similar to those of philosophers of the first generation of ordinary language, like J. Austin, H. P. Grice, and Wittgenstein in the Philosophical Investigations.

In the last chapter of the book, Chapter 9, Stebbing, Phi-losophy and Linguistics, Chapman shows us, in a very clear way, the relations between Stebbing’s work and the follow-ing developments in Philosophy of Language and the dis-cussions of language in general. Throughout her work, it is possible to identify several passages when Stebbing sustains positions that only some years later were systematically con-sidered. As Chapman says “her attentiveness to how words, even the most philosophically loaded ones, are used and understood in everyday life inevitably invites comparisons with ordinary language philosophy. Her insistence that analysis must have real examples of language in use, have resonances with some very recent approaches in linguistics, particularly with critical discourse analysis”. Stebbing’s handbooks on logic, A Modern Introduction to Logic and A Modern Elementary Logic, consider both the analysis of mathematic logic as well the ordinary language, the com-mon sense language.

Susan Stebbing and the Language of Common Sense is a book that deserves attention. It is a very interesting book that brings us important information about the develop-ment of analytical philosophy in the beginning of the twen-tieth century in Britain. Chapman organized the book in a chronologically way that helps the reader to understand the development of Stebbing’s ideas. The language and the way in which the philosophical conceptions are presented are quite clear. In special, in my opinion, this book has as a great worth the capacity to find on a nearly forgotten phi-losopher views that are actual. Although today Stebbing is unfamiliar for most philosophical students, in her works we can find very stimulating analysis and views that remain current. Stebbing contributed to the development of logic and philosophy of language, so her writings cannot be dis-regarded. According to Chapman (p. 186) “Stebbing’s work as a whole is best assessed in relation to the various direc-tions taken in the decades that followed her death by the serious study of human language”. Furthermore, her histor-ical figure is symbolic in the pursuit for equal rights be-tween men and women not only in the universities, but in all fields.

Referências

CHAPMAN, S. Susan Stebbing and the Language of Common Sense. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.

Kariel Antonio Giarolo – Doutor em Filosofia pela Universidade Federal de Santa Maria (UFSM), Santa Maria, RS, Brasil.  E-mail: [email protected]

Acessar publicação original

Wise Women – Reflections of Teachers of Midlife – FREEMAN; SCHMIDT (CSS)

FREEMAN, Phyllis R.; SCHMIDT, Jan Zlotnik (eds). Wise Women – Reflections of Teachers of Midlife. New York: Routledge, 2000. 274p. Resenha de: SENGER, Elizbeth. Canadian Social Studies, v.36, n.2, 2002.

This book is a collection of reflective essays by long term post-secondary instructors, all female, who have now reached midlife. They offer an insightful variety of perspectives some positive, some rather bitter on the challenges and rewards of teaching careers. For the most part, these educators speak in clear language, full of emotion and heartfelt sentiment, about how the educational process has changed them both professionally and personally. One theme which remains constant throughout is that these women freely chose the education profession and clearly understand the importance of this lifelong work.

Wise Women will appeal to anyone, male or female, who has an interest in the educational experience from the instructor’s perspective and should be in any educator’s professional development library. Although some of the reflections are personal, they all evaluate the personal and professional lives of the writers’, sharing what they have learned to do and not do; sharing the greatest rewards and greatest heartbreaks of their careers, and in some cases, of their personal lives. After reading this book the reader will take away a very clear message about education: that teaching and learning, for all of the parties involved, is an ongoing process in which understandings of strategies, techniques, students and selves is continuously evolving and that it is not a process confined to classrooms or hallowed halls. The impact of educational experiences overflows into all aspects of the lives of those involved.

An interesting element of Wise Women is that very few of the contributors focused on the curriculum they teach, but rather discussed at length the process, the gaining of patience, the deepening understanding of themselves and their students. This truly is a book about living, learning and growing as human beings which the profession of teaching and learning encompasses in a most meaningful way.

The editors asked the writers to reflect upon their teaching careers. This is a valuable, perhaps even necessary process for educators to go through. Each year I teach, I find myself continually evaluating the students in my class (each group may be totally different, as some of the writers pointed out) and how I need to adapt my classroom environment and techniques to help them learn. Given the plethora of new ideas and techniques with which educators are bombarded, it is essential to continually examine what we do, how and why we do it, and to be open to the possibilities of adapting and/or adopting new methods, techniques and strategies, as well as retaining the good processes we have already developed. Personal reflection can certainly be a rewarding, and at times, painful experience and it speaks to the courage of these women that they rose to the challenge set before them. It is clear from their reminiscences that these educators went through many phases of growth in their long and distinguished careers. There is some bitterness and resentment in these contributions, as women still, in the twentieth (now twenty first) century, experience the small mindedness of discrimination on campuses across North America. Clearly, as progressive as the field of education may be, we still have a great deal of work to do in opening peoples’ minds to the value of integrating the talents and abilities of fully half the population. This is one of the important actions we, as educators, need to take and reading this book makes that even more clear.

I believe the significance of this book in focusing on midlife teachers is, in part, to provide assistance for those of us who come after these women; to continue learning how to cope with the vast and varied challenges that education presents. The contributors managed to deal effectively with internal and external changes, but often the struggle has taken its toll. In other cases, some of the writers make the point that while the world around them, and their external appearances may have changed, their inside selves have remained dynamic, young, energetic, and enthusiastic things which all teachers need to do their jobs with joy and love, and I believe, to be truly effective. Teaching at any level is not for the faint of heart!

Teaching and learning is as much about learning how to cope with constant change as it is presenting an established curriculum. While very few of these women focused on, or even mentioned, what curriculum they teach, they all had a great deal to say about the physical and psychological environments in which they work. Human interactions; increasing understanding of self and others; adapting teaching techniques to changing students and changing times; learning to balance personal and professional needs; these are the things which this book deals with so effectively, and it is an essential read for anyone who is, has been, or desires to become that much maligned, but very essential professional a teacher.

Elizabeth Senger – Henry Wise Wood High School. Calgary Alberta.

Acessar publicação original

[IF]