Kant on the Rationality of Morality – GUYER (M)

GUYER, Paul. Kant on the Rationality of Morality. Cambridge University Press, 2019. 73pp. Resenha de: CARVALHO, Vinicius. Manuscrito, Campinas, v.43 n.2 Apr./June 2020.

In his contribution to the Cambridge Elements: The Philosophy of Immanuel Kant series, Paul Guyer contends that Kant derives the fundamental principle of morality (in this case, the formulas of the categorical imperative) and the object of morality (the highest good) from the application of the most fundamental principles of reason: the principle of noncontradiction, of sufficient reason, and, to a lesser extent, the principle of excluded middle. The fundamental fact that ought not to be denied by any rational agent – on pain of self-contradiction – is that oneself and others have a free will, in other words, that they have the capacity to freely set and pursue their own ends. Guyer argues that Kant grounds his whole moral theory upon this fact, and that the application of the fundamental principles of reason to it gives us the principle and the object of morality. In what follows, I will summarize each of the book’s chapters, discussing some of its claims when I see fit.

In the second chapter – Reasons, Reasoning and Reason as Such, the first chapter being the introduction  Guyer discusses past approaches about the relation between the fundamental principles of morality and reason for Kant. For instance, philosophers such as Christine Korsgaard and Allen Wood emphasize that rational actions are actions based on reasons, and that genuine reasons are universally valid norms, valid for everyone, everywhere. Kant would have gotten the requirement to act on universally valid reasons from the observation that this is what characterizes rational action. Onora O’Neill also emphasizes the same requirement for universalizability, though she supports her reading not by appealing to the notion of a reason in particular, but to the notion of reasoning in general, in her well-known account of Kant’s conception of reason in the Canon of Pure Reason from the first Critique2. In my view, Guyer correctly criticizes an aspect of O’Neill’s reading on this point: it is not the case that we “invent and construct standards for reasoned thinking and acting”3all the way downPace O’Neill, Guyer argues that it is certainly the case that Kant did not believe that the application of the principles of rationality were sufficient to arrive at substantive metaphysical conclusions: this is one of the features of dogmatism he so fiercely denounced. But he certainly regarded some formal principles of reason as “necessary conditions of reasoning because they are the fundamental principles of reason” (p. 9). So, even though Guyer agrees with these interpreters about the importance of the requirement of universality when it comes to morality, his argument will be that this requirement is the result of the application of some even more fundamental principles, beginning with that of noncontradiction.

The third chapter – From Noncontradiction to Universalizability – shows exactly how that is so. First, Guyer shows that Kant followed the philosophical tradition of his time in accepting the principle of noncontradiction as the first principle of reason (and the principle of sufficient reason as the second). Indeed, Kant is quite clear on this matter in his lectures on Logic (especially in the Jäsche Logik) and at some points in the first Critique4. But to which concepts and pairs of judgment need we apply this principle to derive the principle of morality? In the preface to the Groundwork, Kant says that for any moral law, its “ground of obligation” must be sought “a priori simply in concepts of pure reason” (GMS, AA 04: 389), and in the second section of the work he clarifies that this a priori concept is the concept of a rational being (GMS, AA 04: 412). More precisely even, it is the concept of a rational agent, which is a rational being with the capacity to act according to the representation of certain laws, for the sake of certain ends (GMS, AA 04: 426-7). According to Guyer:

Kant’s argument will then be that the fundamental principle of morality can be derived from the application of the principle of noncontradiction to the concept of a rational agent as one capable of setting its own ends. This capacity must be affirmed of any rational agent and cannot be denied without contradiction. (p. 17)

Guyer’s point is that a maxim is immoral whenever its proposed action entails some belief that contradicts the fact that agents have free will. Take the lying promise situation – in which an agent makes a promise with no intention of keeping it – as an example. Kant says that in such a world, in which everyone makes lying promises whenever it suits their interests, no one would accept promises at all. The practice of making promises in general would cease to exist because one of its necessary conditions (i.e., that the promisee trusts the promisor) is gone. Thus, in making a false promise an agent virtually robs the possibility of everyone else making any promises. It undermines their freedom by making it impossible for them to take part in a social practice in which they have chosen to participate5. It treats other people as if they were not fully free agents. According to Guyer, this shows that “the necessity of avoiding contradiction between a proposed maxim and its universalization is a consequence of the necessity of avoiding contradicting the nature of rational beings as persons with free will” (p. 24). Although Kant does not explicitly say this in the Groundwork, Guyer takes as textual evidence (a) the fact that Kant says of immoral maxims that when universalized they either contradict themselves, or that they entail practices that are inconsistent with some fundamental characteristic of rational agents (see GMS, AA 04: 423-4), and (b) Kant’s treatment of the duties not to commit suicide, to help others in need, and to develop one’s talents in the Metaphysics of Morals (see MS, AA 06: 451; 453).

Since Kant’s treatment of duties in that latter work relies more heavily on the Formula of Humanity (FH) rather than the Formula of Universal Law (FUL), because the nature of rational agents as free agents (ends-in-themselves) is explicit in the former formula, Guyer says: “Thus Kant’s requirement of universalizability follows from the formula of humanity and is ultimately grounded in the law of noncontradiction because the latter is.” (p. 23). I believe this deserved a bit more clarification by the author, though, for the question “how could the requirement of universalizability expressed by FUL follow from FH if the latter is presented after and as a ‘development’ of the first formula?” comes straight to the reader’s mind. A possible answer would be that the derivation of FUL already relies upon the premise that rational agents are free agents, who express their freedom in their adoption of maxims. The evidence for this is Kant’s distinction, already at the beginning of the derivation, between imperfect and perfect wills (GMS, AA 04: 412). It is precisely because rational agents with imperfect wills are free to adopt whatever maxims they propose to themselves that the principle of morality – to choose only maxims apt for universal legislation – is presented as an imperative. In any case, I believe this point should have been more fully developed by the author. The chapter ends with a brief treatment of Kant’s deduction of the freedom of the will at the third section of the Groundwork, where Kant argues that we cannot but regard ourselves as beings with free will when we apply the distinction (argued for in the first Critique) between world of sense and intellectual world. The fact that we know that we are free agents (from the practical point of view) is what produces a self-contradiction whenever we adopt a maxim that entails some belief or other that is inconsistent with this knowledge.

The fourth chapter – The Principle of Sufficient Reason and the Idea of the Highest Good – shows how Kant got his conception of the highest good through the application of the second fundamental principle of reason, that is, the principle of sufficient reason, according to which there is an adequate explanation for every fact. Guyer first discusses how Kant refuses the traditional use of this principle as it was employed by the rationalists, for the application of this principle is warranted only within the limits of possible experience. But, according to Guyer, he accepted the use of this principle when it came to matters of morality. More precisely, Kant claimed that the application of this principle lets us theorize about the “unconditional”, which, in this case, means that we can apply this principle to think about the complete and systematic consequences of morality. For Kant, this means that we are drawn to the idea of the highest good, a condition in which “universal happiness [is] combined with and in conformity with the purest morality throughout the world.” (TP, AA 08: 279).

Throughout the chapter, Guyer defends his interpretation on how to read Kant’s conception of the highest good and his argument for it. He shows that Kant applies this principle in two ways: first, to show that morality is a condition on the pursuit of happiness. Kant does not ground moral worth in possible or actual good consequences of actions. Some action might bring a great deal of happiness (whatever we understand ‘happiness’ to mean), but its accomplishment is constrained by moral considerations, such as if it respects the nature of those involved as ends-in-themselves. In the second case, happiness is conceived as the complete object of morality: since happiness is the satisfaction of all possible ends (GMS, AA 04: 418; KpV, AA 05: 25) and the nature of rational agents is that they set themselves their ends, then “the moral command to preserve and promote the capacity to set ends is in fact equivalent to a moral command to promote happiness … [happiness is] what morality commands in the first instance, but not, as it turns out, all that it commands” (p. 37). This is why, in Kant’s words, “pure practical reason … seeks the unconditioned totality of the object of pure practical reason, under the name of the highest good” (KpV, AA 05: 108). It is important to keep in mind here that happiness commanded by morality under the concept of the highest good is not happiness simpliciter, that is, the mere satisfaction of contingent ends, but that it is limited by moral considerations. This conception of the highest good as the object of morality also leads Kant to develop what he thinks to be the necessary conditions for the attainment of this object. The three ideas of pure reason that were discussed in the Dialectic of the first Critique now receive the status of postulates of practical reason: the immortality of the soul, freedom of the will and the existence of God are propositions that, for Kant, cannot be theoretically proven, but which we must accept because they are necessary conditions to the realization of morality’s object, the highest good. The end of the chapter is devoted to show how Kant eventually shifted position regarding the role of the postulates, especially in his latter writings from the 1790’s.

In the fifth chapter – Rationality and the System of Duties -, Guyer argues that Kant’s treatment of duties show that he also took the ideal of systematicity to be part of his conception of reason and rationality. That this ideal is essential to Kant’s philosophy is clear from the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic (see KrV A 642/B 670), and in his practical philosophy we can see this ideal at work in many occasions. First, there is the requirement that an agent adopts not only one maxim apt for universal legislation, but that all his maxims satisfy this requirement (GMS, AA 04: 432). Second, there is the requirement that all ends of all agents be compatible, as well as that each agent be treated as an end-in-itself, as expressed in the Formula of the Realm of Ends (GMS, AA 04: 433). And third, there is the suggestion that the supreme principle of morality must be able to offer a complete division and characterization of the generally recognized classes of duties6, that is, into (a) perfect and imperfect duties (GMS, AA 04: 423-4), and (b) both duties of virtue (noncoercively enforceable) as well as duties of right (coercively enforceable). Granted, Kant seems to use in general two different principles to derive these duties, focusing on FUL in the Groundwork and on FH in the Metaphysics of Morals. But, as Guyer argues, these principles are supposed to be interchangeable and at least coextensive when it comes to the duties they entail. The most important point of the chapter, however, is the explanation of why we might need a system of duties. Showing that Kant followed in important aspects George F. Meier’s treatment of duties, Guyer argues that the systematic classification of duties, combined with the application of the principles of noncontradiction and excluded middle – the principle that ought implies can as well, but this one is not usually explicitly stated by Kant – are what allows Kant to deny the possibility of conflict of duties, in other words, genuine moral dilemmas. Thus, Guyer says:

Here is where Kant might have brought in the principle of the excluded middle as well as that of noncontradiction: whereas the latter principle tells us that two contrary duties, that is, duties to perform two incompatible acts at the same time, cannot both be duties (on the ground that we cannot have an obligation to perform the impossible), the former would tell us that we have to perform one of these duties. (p. 47)

This chapter ends with a discussion of Kant’s ideal of systematicity both in the theoretical and in the practical uses of reason as presented mainly in the third Critique.

The sixth chapter – Reason as Motivation – explains how, for Kant, pure reason can motivate action. Guyer shows that Kant’s disagreement with Hume about the role of reason in action, though substantial, is not complete. Whereas Hume thought that reason was motivationally inert and could not lead us to action – only sentiments and “passions” could -, Kant thought that pure reason could be practical. Indeed, this is necessary for any action to have moral worth: “What is essential to any moral worth of actions is that the moral law determine the will immediately” (KpV, AA 05: 71). But this does not mean that reason motivates us to action without any feelings being involved, for Kant also says that “every determination of choice proceeds from the representation of a possible action to the deed through the feeling of pleasure and displeasure, taking an interest in the action or its effect” (MS, AA 06: 399). Guyer explains this apparent inconsistency by arguing that we must place Kant’s theory of motivation within his transcendental idealism, specifically the distinction between noumenal and phenomenal selves. The moral law does determine the will immediately because this happens when we choose to adopt the moral law as our “fundamental maxim” (RGV, AA 06: 36) and when we are conscious of it “whenever we draw up maxims of the will for ourselves” (KpV, AA 05: 29). But when it comes to choosing particular maxims, this happens through the intermediation of the feeling of respect, which is a self-wrought feeling, caused by reason, that acts as a counterweight in favor of the moral law against the motivational pull of inclinations (GMS, AA 04: 401). Thus, Guyer says that “reason produces action – this is Kant’s disagreement with Hume – but it does so through the production or modification of feeling – here is Kant’s agreement with Hume” (p. 53). In the rest of the chapter, Guyer discusses Kant’s fuller theory of motivation as presented in the Metaphysics of Morals, which involves the exercise and cultivation of a class of feelings that are sensible to the determination for action through the concept of duty, namely: moral feeling, conscience, love of others or sympathy, and self-respect or self-esteem. Thus, Guyer joins others who have consistently pointed out that any interpretation that represents Kant’s ethics as devoid of any place for feelings and emotions is seriously flawed.

In the seventh chapter – Kantian Constructivism -, Guyer discusses the metaethical implications of his interpretation, especially in the realism versus antirealism debate concerning Kant’s moral theory. Appropriately, the author first makes sure to distinguish semantic realism from ontological realism. This fundamental distinction is unfortunately not always drawn in discussions of Kant’s metaethics, causing many unnecessary disagreements. Guyer claims that Kant is clearly a semantic realist: for him, judgments about right and wrong, good or bad, are not indeterminate in their truth-value, and they can be correctly inferred from previous moral judgments and principles. In other words, there are correct and incorrect answers to moral questions, i.e., questions of permissibility, worthiness, etc. The real hornet’s nest is when it comes to the following problem: in virtue of what are some moral judgments true? Is it due to some metaphysical fact independent of us, or is it the result of the application of some constructive procedure?

The latter position was famously defended by John Rawls, who labeled the method employed in his political philosophy Kantian Constructivism. Defenders of a constructivist reading of Kant’s metaethics claim that he derived the principles of morality from a mere conception of practical reason or reason in general. On the other hand, those who prefer the (ontological) realist view say that what ultimately grounds morality and from which Kant derives its principles is the fact that rational agents are ends in themselves, “or that human freedom is intrinsically valuable” (p. 64). As Guyer points out, and I am in very much agreement with him on this point, the method by which Kant derives particular moral duties constitutes a form of constructivism: we infer particular duties by applying the different formulas of the moral law to our specific circumstances7. Therefore, we can say that Kant is a normative constructivist.8 But it is not so clear whether he is a metaethical constructivist. Some argue that what grounds the moral law is the fact that rational agents are free, which gives them an irreducible value, outside the purview of construction, upon which morality is grounded9. For Guyer, Kant’s position regarding the nature of the fundamental principle of morality should be seen as a realist position: this fundamental principle is ultimately derived from the application of the principle of noncontradiction to the fact that rational agents have free wills, a fact that obtains independently of any procedure of construction. But he claims that this does not fit well with what we contemporarily regard as moral realism, for this fact is not a specific moral one, nor is it Kant’s position that there is something of value in the world independent of evaluative attitudes. About this, Guyer says:

This is a fact, in Kant’s own words a “fact of reason”, but it is not a mysterious moral fact, or a value that somehow exists in the universe independently of our act of valuing it. It is simply a fact that cannot be denied on pain of self-contradiction, since, Kant assumes, in some way we always recognize it even when by our actions we would deny it. Whether Kant succeeded in demonstrating this fact is a question; but there is no question that he regards our possessions of wills as a fact from which moral theory must begin. Thus we can say that as regards its fundamental principle, Kant’s moral philosophy is a form of realism, though not specifically moral realism. (p. 64)

As the author points out both in this last chapter and in the second, it is one thing for Kant to show how the principles and the final object of morality are derived from the fact that we are free agents combined with the requirement to respect the fundamental principles of reason; it is quite another thing for him to demonstrate that we are, indeed, free agents. That would be the subject of a much longer and detailed study, which falls out of the scope of the book, let alone of this review. Kant on the Rationality of Morality is a short but insightful book. Its discussions bridge Kant’s theoretical and practical philosophies, and they offer an original argument for one of the most important interpretative problems of the Groundwork, the derivation of the principles of morality. I recommend it especially to those who prefer to read Kant’s ethics as not so dependent on the significant metaphysical and epistemological theses of his transcendental idealism; as well, of course, to those interested in moral theory in general.

References

Kant, I. Gesammelte Schriften. Hrsg.: Bd. 1-22 Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 23 Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, ab Bd. 24 Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen: Berlin, 1900ff. [ Links ]

_____ “The Jäsche Logik”. (Log). In: Lectures on Logic. Translated by J. Michael Jung. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. [ Links ]

_____ Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. (GMS) Translated by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann. Cambrigde: Cambridge University Press, 2011. [ Links ]

_____ Critique of Pure Reason. (KrV). Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. [ Links ]

_____ “Metaphysics of Morals”. (MS) In: Practical Philosophy. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. [ Links ]

_____ “Critique of Practical Reason”. (KrV) In: Practical Philosophy. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. [ Links ]

_____ “On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but is of no use in practice”. (TP) In: Practical Philosophy. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. [ Links ]

_____ Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. (RGV) Translated by Allen Wood and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. [ Links ]

Herman, B. “Leaving Deontology Behind”. In: The Practice of Moral Judgement. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, 1993, pp. 208-240. [ Links ]

Korsgaard, C. The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora O’Neill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press , 1996. [ Links ]

Timmons, M. “The Categorical Imperative and Universalizability”. In: HORN, C; SCHÖNECKER, D. (eds.) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2006, pp. 158-199. [ Links ]

O’Neill, O. Constructions of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press , 1989. [ Links ]

_____ “Autonomy, Plurality and Public Reason”. In: BRENDER, N; KRASNOFF, L. (eds.) New Essays on the History of Autonomy: A Collection Honoring J. B. Schneewind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, pp. 181-194. [ Links ]

Schönecker, D; Schmidt, E. “Kant’s Moral Realism regarding Dignity and Value: Some Comments on the Tugendlehre.” In: SANTOS, R; SCHMIDT, E. (eds.) Realism and Antirealism in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter , 2018, pp. 119-152. [ Links ]

Street. S. “Constructivism about Reasons” In: SHAFER-LANDAU, R. (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 3, 2008, pp. 207-245. [ Links ]

Wood, A. Kantian Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press , 2008. [ Links ]

Notas

1This work was supported by grant 2019/21992-8, São Paulo Research Foundation (FAPESP).

2 O’Neill, 1989.

3 O’Neill, 2004, p. 187.

4Log, AA 9: 51 and KrV, A 150/B 189; A 151-2/B 191. References to Kant’s texts follow the standard: abbreviation of the work, followed by their number in the Akademie volumes and their corresponding pagination. Except for the Critique of Pure Reason, quoted with reference to the pagination of its first (A) and second (B) editions. All quotations of Kant are taken from the Cambridge editions.

5 Barbara Herman (1993, p. 215) gives a similar explanation: “A condition of choice that could not be accepted by all rational agents would be: doing x where the possibility of x-ing depends on other rational agents similarly situated not doing x. This is the condition standardly found to be the ground of choice of the deceitful-promise maxim”.

6Right after stating FUL, Kant says: “Now, if from this one imperative all imperatives of duty can be derived as from their principle, then, even though we leave it unsettled whether what is called duty is not such an empty concept, we shall at least be able to indicate what we think by it and what the concept means” (GMS, AA 04: 421). For an argument that FUL cannot adequately provide a general classification of duties, see Timmons (2004).

7“ … moral philosophy … gives him [the human being], as a rational being, laws a priori; which of course still require a power of judgment sharpened by experience <durch Erfahrung geschärfte Urtheilskraft>, partly to distinguish in what cases they are applicable, partly to obtain for them access to the will of a human being and momentum for performance …” (GMS, AA 04: 389). See also MS, AA 06: 217.

8I am borrowing this notion from Street (2008).

9For such a realist reading of Kant, see Schönecker and Schmidt (2018).

Vinicius Carvalho – University of Campinas Department of Philosophy Campinas – S.P. Brazil [email protected]

Acessar publicação original

Sem fins lucrativos: por que a democracia precisa das humanidades – NUSSBAUM (C)

NUSSBAUM, Martha. Sem fins lucrativos: por que a democracia precisa das humanidades. São Paulo: M. Fontes, 2015. Resenha de: CESCON, Everaldo. Conjectura, Caxias do Sul, v. 21, n. 2, p. 461-466, maio/ago, 2016.

Ensinar a ser homens de negócios ou cidadãos responsáveis? Treinar para obter lucros ou educar à cultura do respeito e da igualdade? É preciso saber interpretar o mundo no qual se vive ou bastam técnicos e cientistas capazes de fazê-lo funcionar? Essas são algumas das questões enfrentadas por Nussbaum, filósofa liberal de tendência reformista e progressista com ascendência aristotélica.

A autora aborda a crise do ensino humanista que, vista em escala mundial, parece prejudicial para o futuro da democracia e das novas gerações. A corrida ao lucro no mercado mundial está dissolvendo a capacidade de pensar criticamente, de transcender os localismos e de enfrentar os problemas mundiais como “cidadãos do mundo”. Leia Mais

Elementos da filosofia moral – RACHELS (C)

RACHELS, James. Elementos da filosofia moral. Trad. de Roberto C. Filho. 4. ed. Barueri: Manole, 2006. Resenha de: BRESOLIN, Keberson. Conjectura, Caxias do Sul, v. 16, n. 1, Jan/Abr, 2011.

Pensar ética é pensar sobre o modo como as pessoas relacionam-se consigo mesmas, com o outro, com a sociedade e em alguns casos, com o sobrenatural e o ambiente. Ou seja, pensar a ética é pensar a totalidade das relações que se desdobram sobre o horizonte da historicidade humana. Isso não é fácil, muito menos simples. E, quando o assunto em pauta é ética, parece que todos entendem; ou ainda, quando não entendem usam um argumento infalível [unfehlbar], qual seja, “a ética é subjetiva, então, depende de cada um”, logo, a contenda é encerrada.

Essa postura, além de relativista, demonstra a necessidade de um estudo profundo e profícuo sobre a ética para, assim, compreender que ela é uma maneira de agir a partir de princípios e/ou valores definitivamente refletidos e fundamentados. A tentativa de James Rachels, no seu livro Elementos da filosofia moral, é exatamente esta: abordar temas centrais do pensamento moral com a finalidade de mostrar seus fundamentos e seus argumentos sejam eles sustentáveis ou não.

Rachels, filósofo norte-americano, nasceu em Columbus, Geórgia em 30.5.1941 e faleceu em 5.9.2003. Proferiu aulas nas seguintes universidades: University of Richmond, New York University e na University of Alabama at Birmingham onde permaneceu por 26 anos. Sua primeira obra intitulada Moral problems (1971), ao ser lançada, contribuiu para que as faculdades norte-americanas repensassem o modelo de ensino da ética, ou seja, nesse momento, nos EUA, a metaética dominava os debates nas universidades, de modo que sua obra contribuiu a que o ensino da ética se voltasse para questões morais de envergadura prática.1

Em 1975, no início dos debates em torno de questões bioéticas, Rachels escreveu um artigo intitulado “Active and passive euthanasia”.

No ano de 1986 aparece, então, o livro The elements of moral philosophy [Elementos da filosofia moral] e, no mesmo ano publica The end of life (1986) e, em seguida, Created from animals2 (1990), Can ethics provide answers? (1997), The legacy of Socrates (2007). Pouco antes de ser diagnosticado com câncer, Rachels conclui seu livro Problems from philosophy, que foi publicado postumamente. Além disso, escreveu inúmeros ensaios e artigos e editou vários livros, mas seu best-seller é, sem sombra de dúvidas, o livro Elementos da filosofia moral.3 Esse livro já está na sua quarta edição no Brasil, justamente por ser um excelente livro de filosofia moral. Apresenta uma linguagem simples, sem deixar de ter argumentos extremamente bem-elaborados. Combina de maneira formidável exemplos práticos com teorias éticas complexas, sem ser, por isso, leviano ou descritivo. Diferentemente de outros livros, os quais abordam a ética com a metodologia por autores, o livro de Rachels aborda temas, dentro dos quais desenvolve os principais autores que abordaram tal assunto. Dessa forma, os temas escolhidos para estigmatizarem os capítulos são postos não com uma preocupação histórico-temporal, mas, a nosso ver, com uma preocupação de inserir e instruir o leitor nos mais importantes debates/temas éticos.

Rachels elaborou 14 capítulos para seu livro, sendo que podemos encontrar nele não apenas questões centrais da milenar ética normativa, mas também questões da jovem metaética. Como todo bom livro, o primeiro capítulo (“O que é a moralidade”?) desenrola uma discussão sobre a natureza da moral. Faz isso de maneira inusitada utilizando-se de três exemplos práticos nos quais a decisão moral não é simples. Os exemplos: a bebê Teresa (bebê anencéfalo), Jodie e Mary (gêmeos siamesas) e Tracy Latimer (vítima de paralisia cerebral), de cunho prático, são apresentados em toda a sua complexidade e dificuldade de resolução.

Depois disso, Rachels apresenta o que ele chama “concepção mínima de moralidade”, a qual, a nosso ver, reflete uma postura utilitarista. A concepção mínima de moralidade é o esforço ou, pelo menos, o esforço para dirigir nossa conduta por razões ou, ainda, fazer aquilo que nos mostre as melhores razões para fazer sem deixar de ser, ao mesmo tempo imparcial, ou seja, considerar os interesses de todos os envolvidos na ação de maneira não parcial. Segundo Rachels, essa é a melhor concepção moral porque ela é mínima, ou seja, aquilo que todos podem igualmente concordar em fazer, não exigindo uma moralidade austera ou ascética do agente.

No segundo capítulo intitulado “O desafio do relativismo cultural”, Rachels aborda de maneira genuína o problema que o relativismo cultural desencadeia para a moral. Primeiramente, o autor se coloca na postura de um relativista cultural de maneira a extrair daí as consequências sérias de ser relativista cultural. Demonstra, então, que não poderíamos criticar outras culturas pelas suas ações e atos, visto que o certo e o errado são relativos de cada cultura em um determinado momento espaciotemporal.

Faz isso utilizando-se de inúmeros exemplos, como a excisão no Togo, as diferentes e antigas práticas funerais entre os gregos e os Calatinos (tribo de indianos). Os exemplos/fatos são algo marcante em toda obra, tornando-a, pois, atraente não apenas a estudantes de ética, mas também a pessoas leigas no assunto que possuem uma centelha de curiosidade pela ética.

“O subjetivismo em ética” é o título do terceiro capítulo, no qual aborda o relativismo em uma dimensão doméstica, ou seja, “particularista-subjetivo”. Aborda, além disso, a questão do sentimento moral e sua nova estruturação dada pelo emotivismo e a complexa questão posta pela oposição cognitivista versus não cognitivista em moral, qual seja, existem ou não fatos morais? No quarto capítulo, “Dependerá a moralidade da religião?”, o autor realiza uma excelente análise sobre a relação religião/moral e como elas se aproximaram ao longo do processo ético-histórico. Rebate categoricamente o fato de algumas pessoas crerem que, se não existir um Deus punidor, então, não há motivo algum para haver ações morais, ou seja, por que agir moralmente se não há castigo, nem vida pós-morte? Ausculta, ainda, a teoria dos mandamentos divinos, demonstrando como esse argumento é carente de fundamentação. Faz isso a partir da célebre afirmação de Sócrates no diálogo Eutifron, no qual se pergunta se o comportamento é correto porque os deuses ordenaram ou os deuses ordenaram porque é correto. Aborda, também, com alguma mazela a teoria da lei natural.

No quinto capítulo aborda “O egoísmo subjetivo” no qual se apropinqua da possibilidade de altruísmo. Mas, a nosso ver, o capítulo sexto intitulado “O egoísmo ético” é muito mais consistente e persuasivo.

Trabalha com argumentos a favor e contra o egoísmo e acaba com o lendário mito de que todo indivíduo egoísta é moralmente mau. Egoísmo é uma concepção moral. Ser egoísta é preservar unicamente seus interesses. No capítulo sétimo “A abordagem utilitarista” e o oitavo “O debate sobre o utilitarismo”, Rachels aborda genialmente o utilitarismo, demonstrando, então, a origem do mesmo e, em seguida, novamente citando vários casos concretos, propõe argumentos prós e contras. Como já dito anteriormente, o livro, segundo nossa leitura, possui um cunho utilitarista leviano, ou seja, não compromete a obra, muito menos a torna tendenciosa. A própria solução apresentada por Rachels ao relativismo cultural, no capítulo segundo, ou seja, um critério neutro de avaliação cultural, apresenta, indiscutivelmente, personalidade utilitarista.

Ao tratar de Kant, nos capítulos nono e décimo, o autor perscruta o âmago da concepção moral kantiana. No capítulo nono, proposto em forma de pergunta (“haverá regras morais absolutas?”), objetifica a moralidade kantiana, demonstrando os dois imperativos: categórico e hipotético. A partir da perspectiva kantiana a resposta à pergunta que originalmente está posta no título do capítulo é sim. Rachels demonstra que o imperativo categórico não suporta exceção e, por isso, toda regra de conduta que surge dele é categoricamente absoluta. Essa regra é apresentada como obrigação da razão e consiste, então, tanto em uma obrigação para fazer como uma obrigação para não fazer alguma ação. O autor trabalha com o famoso texto kantiano “Sobre o suposto direito de mentir por amor à humanidade” para enfatizar a absolutidade das regras categóricas, inclusive, em momentos nos quais a mentira poderia salvar uma vida. O capítulo décimo “Kant e o respeito pelas pessoas” não foi feliz como o anterior. Deixa a desejar na concepção kantiana de dignidade humana. Utiliza-se de uma interpretação da qual não pensamos ser kantiana o suficiente para abarcar a profundidade de tal percepção.

A seguir, Rachels, junto com Hobbes, expõe “A ideia de contrato social” (título do décimo primeiro capítulo), no qual ratifica o paradigma do filósofo britânico ao afirmar o caráter não social e egoísta do homem.

A natureza fez os homens tão iguais que é inevitável o conflito, uma vez que as necessidades são semelhantes, e os recursos, finitos, sendo, pois, necessário um Estado poderoso, o Leviatã, para administrar tais conflitos.

Apresenta também o famigerado dilema do prisioneiro para assoalhar que a decisão fundamentada em princípios cooperativos é a melhor escolha.

No capítulo décimo segundo “Feminismo e a ética do cuidado”, Rachels analisa um tema recente em filosofia moral. A partir dos estágios propostos pelo psicólogo Lawrence Kohlberg e de suas constatações realizadas a partir do “dilema de Heinz” de que o menino estaria em nível superior de moralidade ao ser comparado com uma menina de mesma idade, Rachels desenrola um debate, com o auxílio das ideias de Carol Gilligan, sobre como há diferença na construção de juízos de valoração entre homens e mulheres. Enquanto os homens prezam por uma ética principialista, a ética feminista possui um cunho de cuidado. Esse capítulo é excelente, porque o autor parte dos diferentes aspectos psicológicos que há entre homens e mulheres para chegar, então, a visualizar como tais diferenças influenciam a construção de juízos de valor.

No penúltimo capítulo, o autor aborda a “Ética das virtudes”. Esse paradigma ético não está preocupado, como enfatiza ele, em formular obrigações morais, mas em compreender o que torna o caráter bom. O que é virtude? Como praticá-las? Quantas são? tornam a preocupação com essa ética diferente das demais, embora continue sendo normativa.

Dessa maneira, o autor demonstra a especificidade da ética das virtudes em relação às éticas dos mandamentos morais, elaborada, principalmente, a partir da modernidade.

No último capítulo, Rachels faz uma reflexão em torno de como seria uma teoria moral satisfatória. Aqui os traços utilitaristas do autor são ainda mais claros. Evidenciando o fato de que existem inúmeras teorias éticas, que são, em muitos casos, incompatíveis entre si, Rachels pergunta-se: como seria uma teoria moral satisfatória? Promover os interesses de todas as pessoas de maneira imparcial, tratando cada uma delas como merecem, ou seja, por serem agentes racionais devem ser tratados sem distinção simplesmente por possuírem o poder de escolha.

Todavia, o autor ressalva que a ideia de promover de forma igual os interesses de todos não parece conseguir captar a amplitude da vida moral, fazendo, pois, uma reserva em relação à questão do merecimento pessoal, ou seja, à consideração das individualidades. Dito isso, o autor comenta as concepções de Smith e o “utilitarismo dos motivos” de Sidgwick, acerca do qual não se mostra simpático e propõe o “utilitarismo de estratégias múltiplas”, ou seja, o fim fundamental continua sendo o bem-estar geral, mas se pode defender estratégias diferentes como meio para buscar esse fim. Consoante Rachels, há aqui uma combinação de métodos, motivos e virtudes de tomada de decisão que será melhor para o agente, considerando as suas circunstâncias, o caráter e as capacidades.

Aqui é necessário pensar melhor no sentido de otimizar as condições de possibilidade de o agente ter uma boa vida, ao mesmo tempo que otimiza as possibilidades de as outras pessoas terem vida boa.

Sem dúvida, o livro Elementos da filosofia moral é uma excelente obra de introdução a questões éticas. Mostra-se de grande valor no ensino da ética, uma vez que isso se torna claro diante da quantidade de casos e exemplos utilizados ao longo de toda obra, sem deixar a desejar, ao mesmo tempo, um conteúdo fundamentado. Não é um livro catequético, pelo contrário, apresenta, na maioria das vezes, argumentos prós e contras à teoria abordada, embora, como já mencionado, segundo nossa leitura, possua um fio condutor utilitarista.

Notas

1 Cf. Disponível em: < http://www.jamesrachels.org/ >. Acesso em: 31 dez. 2010.

2 Rachels arguiu a favor do vegetarianismo moral e dos direitos dos animais. Neste livro Created from Animals, ele assevera que a visão de mundo darwinista tem implicações filosóficas fundamentais e [deveria] altera[r] o modo como tratamos os animais não humanos. 3 Cf. Disponível em: < http://www.jamesrachels.org/ >. Acesso em: 31 dez. 2010.

Keberson Bresolin – Doutorando em Filosofia pela Pontifícia Universidade do Rio Grande do Sul.

Acessar publicação original